Logic: Logic in Coq
Like its built-in programming language, Coq's built-in
logic is extremely small: universal quantification (forall)
and implication (->) are primitive, but all the other familiar logical
connectives -- conjunction, disjunction, negation,
existential quantification, even equality -- can be defined
using just these and Inductive.
The logical conjunction of propositions A and B is
represented by the following inductively defined
proposition.
Note that, like the definition of ev, this definition
is parameterized; however, in this case, the parameters are
themselves propositions.
The intuition behind this definition is simple: to
construct evidence for and A B, we must provide evidence
for A and evidence for B. More precisely:
- conj e1 e2 can be taken as evidence for and A B if e1
is evidence for A and e2 is evidence for B; and
- this is the only way to give evidence for and A B -- that is, if someone gives us evidence for and A B, we know it must have the form conj e1 e2, where e1 is evidence for A and e2 is evidence for B.
Since we'll be using conjunction a lot, let's introduce a more
familiar-looking infix notation for it.
(The type_scope annotation tells Coq that this notation
will be appearing in propositions, not values.)
Consider the "type" of the constructor conj
(* Check conj. *)
Notice that it "takes 4 inputs", namely the propositions
A,B and evidence of A, B, and "returns as output", the
evidence of A /\ B.
See if you can predict the induction principle for conjunction.
(* Check and_ind. *)
☐
Besides the elegance of building everything up from a
tiny foundation, what's nice about defining conjunction this
way is that we can prove statements involving conjunction
using the tactics that we already know. For example, if the
goal statement is a conjuction, we can prove it by applying
the single constructor conj, which (as can be seen from the
type of conj) solves the current goal and leaves the two
parts of the conjunction as subgoals to be proved
separately.
Theorem and_example :
(ev 0) /\ (ev 4).
Proof.
apply conj.
Case "left". apply ev_0.
Case "right". apply ev_SS. apply ev_SS. apply ev_0. Qed.
Let's take a look at the proof object for the above theorem.
(* Print and_example. *)
Note that the proof is of the form
conj (ev 0) (ev 4) (Pf of ev 0) (Pf of ev 4)
which is what you'd expect, given the type of conj
conj (ev 0) (ev 4) (Pf of ev 0) (Pf of ev 4)
which is what you'd expect, given the type of conj
The split tactic is a convenient shorthand for apply conj.
Theorem and_example' :
(ev 0) /\ (ev 4).
Proof.
split.
Case "left". apply ev_0.
Case "right". apply ev_SS. apply ev_SS. apply ev_0. Qed.
Conversely, the inversion tactic can be used to investigate
a conjunction hypothesis in the context and calculate what
evidence must have been used to build it.
Theorem proj1 : forall A B : Prop,
A /\ B -> A.
Proof.
intros A B H.
inversion H as [HA HB].
apply HA. Qed.
☐
Theorem and_commut : forall A B : Prop,
A /\ B -> B /\ A.
Proof.
intros A B H.
split.
Case "left". apply proj2 with (A:=A). apply H.
Case "right". apply proj1 with (B:=B). apply H. Qed.
Notice the nested inversion breaks H : A /\ (B /\ C) down
into HA: A, HB : B and HC : C. Finish the proof from
there:
Theorem and_assoc : forall A B C : Prop,
A /\ (B /\ C) -> (A /\ B) /\ C.
Proof.
intros A B C H.
inversion H as [HA [HB HC]].
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Now we can prove the other direction of the equivalence of
even and ev. Notice that the left-hand conjunct here is
the statement we are actually interested in; the right-hand
conjunct is needed in order to make the induction hypothesis
strong enough that we can carry out the reasoning in the
inductive step. (To see why this is needed, try proving the
left conjunct by itself and observe where things get
stuck.)
Theorem even_ev : forall n : nat,
(even n -> ev n) /\ (even (S n) -> ev (S n)).
Proof.
(* Hint: Use induction on n. *)
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
The familiar logical "if and only if" is just the
conjunction of two implications.
Definition iff (A B : Prop) := (A -> B) /\ (B -> A).
Notation "A <-> B" := (iff A B) (at level 95, no associativity) : type_scope.
Theorem iff_implies : forall A B : Prop,
(A <-> B) -> A -> B.
Proof.
intros A B H.
inversion H as [HAB HBA]. apply HAB. Qed.
Theorem iff_sym : forall A B : Prop,
(A <-> B) -> (B <-> A).
Proof.
intros A B H.
inversion H as [HAB HBA].
split. (* Note that split is just a bit smarter than apply conj,
which would have required an unfold iff first. *)
Case "->". apply HBA.
Case "<-". apply HAB. Qed.
Using the above proof that <-> is symmetric (iff_sym) as
a guide, prove that it is also reflexive and transitive.
Hint: If you have an iff hypothesis in the context, you
can use inversion to break it into two separate
implications. (Think about why this works.)
Theorem iff_trans : forall A B C : Prop,
(A <-> B) -> (B <-> C) -> (A <-> C).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
We have seen that the families of propositions MyProp and
ev actually characterize the same set of numbers (the even
ones). Prove that MyProp n <-> ev n for all
n (MyProp_iff_ev in Logic.v). Just for fun, write your
proof as an explicit proof object, rather than using
tactics.
☐
Unfortunately, propositions phrased with <-> are a
bit inconvenient to use as hypotheses or lemmas, because they
have to be deconstructed into their two directed components
in order to be applied. (The basic problem is that there's
no way to apply an iff proposition directly. If it's a
hypothesis, you can invert it, which is tedious; if it's a
lemma, you have to destruct it into hypotheses, which is
worse.) Consequently, many Coq developments avoid <->,
despite its appealing compactness. It can actually be made
much more convenient using a Coq feature called "setoid
rewriting," but that is a bit beyond the scope of this
course.
Disjunction ("logical or") can also be defined as an
inductive proposition.
Inductive or (A B : Prop) : Prop :=
| or_introl : A -> or A B
| or_intror : B -> or A B.
Notation "A \/ B" := (or A B) : type_scope.
See if you can predict the induction principle for disjunction.
(* Check or_ind. *)
☐
Consider the "type" of the constructor or_introl
(* Check or_introl. *)
Notice that it "takes 3 inputs", namely the propositions
A,B and evidence of A, and "returns as output", the
evidence of A /\ B. Next, look at the "type" of
or_intror
(* Check or_intror. *)
It is like or_introl but instead of evidence of A,
requires evidence of B
Intuition: There are two ways of giving evidence for A \/ B:
- give evidence for A (and say that it is A you are
giving evidence for! -- this is the function of the
or_introl constructor)
- give evidence for B, tagged with the or_intror constructor.
Since A \/ B has two constructors, doing inversion on a
hypothesis of type A \/ B yields two subgoals.
Theorem or_commut : forall A B : Prop,
A \/ B -> B \/ A.
Proof.
intros A B H.
inversion H as [HA | HB].
Case "left". apply or_intror. apply HA.
Case "right". apply or_introl. apply HB. Qed.
From here on, we'll use the handy tactics left and right
in place of apply or_introl and apply or_intror.
Theorem or_commut' : forall A B : Prop,
A \/ B -> B \/ A.
Proof.
intros A B H.
inversion H as [HA | HB].
Case "left". right. apply HA.
Case "right". left. apply HB. Qed.
Theorem or_distributes_over_and_1 : forall A B C : Prop,
A \/ (B /\ C) -> (A \/ B) /\ (A \/ C).
Proof.
intros A B C. intros H. inversion H as [HA | [HB HC]].
Case "left". split.
SCase "left". left. apply HA.
SCase "right". left. apply HA.
Case "right". split.
SCase "left". right. apply HB.
SCase "right". right. apply HC. Qed.
Theorem or_distributes_over_and_2 : forall A B C : Prop,
(A \/ B) /\ (A \/ C) -> A \/ (B /\ C).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(A \/ B) /\ (A \/ C) -> A \/ (B /\ C).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Theorem or_distributes_over_and : forall A B C : Prop,
A \/ (B /\ C) <-> (A \/ B) /\ (A \/ C).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
A \/ (B /\ C) <-> (A \/ B) /\ (A \/ C).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
We've already seen several places where analogous
structures can be found in Coq's computational (Type) and
logical (Prop) worlds. Here is one more: the boolean
operators andb and orb are obviously analogs, in some
sense, of the logical connectives /\ and \/. This
analogy can be made more precise by the following theorems,
which show how to "translate" knowledge about andb and
orb's behaviors on certain inputs into propositional facts
about those inputs.
Theorem andb_true : forall b c,
andb b c = true -> b = true /\ c = true.
Proof.
intros b c H.
destruct b.
destruct c.
apply conj. reflexivity. reflexivity.
inversion H.
inversion H. Qed.
Prove these properties relating operations on booleans and
logical connectives in Prop.
Theorem andb_false : forall b c,
andb b c = false -> b = false \/ c = false.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem orb_true : forall b c,
orb b c = true -> b = true \/ c = true.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem orb_false : forall b c,
orb b c = false -> b = false /\ c = false.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Logical falsehood can be represented in Coq as an inductively
defined proposition with no constructors.
Intuition: False is a proposition for which there is no way
to give evidence.
Can you predict the induction principle for falsehood?
(* Check False_ind. *)
☐
Since False has no constructors, inverting it always
yields zero subgoals, allowing us to immediately prove any
goal.
Theorem False_implies_nonsense :
False -> plus 2 2 = 5.
Proof.
intros contra.
inversion contra. Qed.
What happened? inversion breaks contra into each of its
possible cases, and yields a subgoal for each case. As
contra is evidence for False, it has no possible cases,
hence, there are no possible subgoals and the proof is
done.
Conversely, the only way to prove False is if there is
already something nonsensical or contradictory in the
context:
Theorem nonsense_implies_False :
plus 2 2 = 5 -> False.
Proof.
intros contra.
inversion contra. Qed.
Actually, since the proof of False_implies_nonsense
doesn't actually have anything to do with the specific
nonsensical thing being proved; it can easily be generalized
to work for an arbitrary P:
Theorem ex_falso_quodlibet : forall (P:Prop),
False -> P.
Proof.
intros P contra.
inversion contra. Qed.
The Latin ex falso quodlibet means, literally, "from
falsehood follows whatever you please." This theorem is also
known as the principle of explosion.
Since we have defined falsehood in Coq, we should also
mention that it is, of course, possible to define truth in
the same way.
Define True as another inductively defined proposition.
What induction principle will Coq generate for your
definition? (The intution is that True should be a
proposition for which it is trivial to give evidence.
Alternatively, you may find it easiest to start with the
induction principle and work backwards to the inductive
definition.)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
However, unlike False, which we'll use extensively,
True is basically a theoretical curiosity: since it is
trivial to prove as a goal, it carries no useful information
as a hypothesis.
The logical complement of a proposition A is written not A or, for
shorthand, ~A:
The intuition is that, if A is not true, then
anything at all (even False) should follow from assuming
A.
It takes a little practice to get used to working with
negation in Coq. Even though you can see perfectly well why
something is true, it can be a little hard at first to figure
out how to get things into the right configuration so that
Coq can see it! Here are proofs of a view familiar facts
about negation to get you warmed up.
Theorem not_False :
~ False.
Proof.
unfold not. intros H. inversion H. Qed.
Theorem contradiction_implies_anything : forall A B : Prop,
(A /\ ~A) -> B.
Proof.
intros A B H. inversion H as [HA HNA]. unfold not in HNA.
apply HNA in HA. inversion HA. Qed.
Theorem double_neg : forall A : Prop,
A -> ~~A.
Proof.
intros A H. unfold not. intros G. apply G. apply H. Qed.
As an exercise, write an informal proof of double_neg:
Theorem: For any prop A, A -> ~~A
Proof: (* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Theorem: For any prop A, A -> ~~A
Proof: (* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Theorem contrapositive : forall A B : Prop,
(A -> B) -> (~B -> ~A).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(A -> B) -> (~B -> ~A).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
☐
Theorem five_not_even :
~ ev 5.
Proof.
unfold not. intros Hev5. inversion Hev5 as [|n Hev3 Heqn].
inversion Hev3 as [|n' Hev1 Heqn']. inversion Hev1. Qed.
Theorem five_not_even in Logic.v confirms the
unsurprising fact that that five is not an even number.
Prove this more interesting fact:
Theorem ev_not_ev_S : forall n,
ev n -> ~ ev (S n).
Proof.
unfold not. intros n H. induction H. (* not n! *)
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
For those who like a challenge, here is an exercise
taken from the Coq'Art book (p. 123). The following five
statements are often considered as characterizations of
classical logic (as opposed to constructive logic, which is
what is "built in" to Coq). We can't prove them in Coq, but
we can consistently add any one of them as an unproven axiom
if we wish to work in classical logic. Prove that these five
propositions are equivalent.
Definition peirce := forall P Q: Prop,
((P->Q)->P)->P.
Definition classic := forall P:Prop,
~~P -> P.
Definition excluded_middle := forall P:Prop,
P \/~P.
Definition de_morgan_not_and_not := forall P Q:Prop,
~(~P/\~Q) -> P\/Q.
Definition implies_to_or := forall P Q:Prop,
(P->Q) -> (~P\/Q).
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Saying x <> y is just the same as saying ~(x = y).
Notation "x <> y" := (~ (x = y)) : type_scope.
Since inequality involves a negation, it again requires
a little practice to be able to work with it fluently. Here
is one very useful trick. If you are trying to prove a goal
that is nonsensical (e.g., the goal state is false = true),
apply the lemma ex_falso_quodlibet to change the goal to
False. This makes it easier to use assumptions of the form
~P that are available in the context -- in particular,
assumptions of the form x<>y.
Theorem not_false_then_true : forall b : bool,
b <> false -> b = true.
Proof.
intros b H. destruct b.
Case "b = true". reflexivity.
Case "b = false".
unfold not in H. (* optional step *)
apply ex_falso_quodlibet.
apply H. reflexivity. Qed.
Theorem not_eq_beq_false : forall n n' : nat,
n <> n'
-> beq_nat n n' = false.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
n <> n'
-> beq_nat n n' = false.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Theorem beq_false_not_eq : forall n m,
false = beq_nat n m -> n <> m.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
false = beq_nat n m -> n <> m.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Another extremely important logical connective is
existential quantification.
Inductive ex (X : Type) (P : X -> Prop) : Prop :=
ex_intro : forall witness:X, P witness -> ex X P.
(* Check ex_intro. *)
The intuition behind this definition is that, in order to
give evidence for the assertion "there exists an x for
which the proposition P holds" we must actually name a
witness -- a specific value x -- and then give evidence
for P x.
We can use Coq's notation definition facility to
introduce more standard notation for writing existentially
quantified propositions, exactly parallel to the built-in
syntax for universally quantified propositions. Instead of
writing (ex nat (fun x => ev x)) to express the proposition
that there exists some number that is even, for example, we
can write exists x:nat, ev x. (It is not necessary to
understand the details of how the definition works.)
Notation "'exists' x , p" := (ex _ (fun x => p))
(at level 200, x ident, right associativity) : type_scope.
Notation "'exists' x : X , p" := (ex _ (fun x:X => p))
(at level 200, x ident, right associativity) : type_scope.
We can use the same tactics as always for manipulate
existentials. For example, if to prove an existential, we
apply the constructor ex_intro. Since the premise of
ex_intro involves a variable (witness) that does not
appear in its conclusion, we need to explicitly give its
value when we use apply.
Example exists_example_1 : exists n, plus n (mult n n)
= 6.
Proof.
apply ex_intro with (witness:=2).
reflexivity. Qed.
Note that we have to explicitly give the witness.
Or, instead of writing apply ex_intro with e, we can write
the convenient shorthand exists e.
Conversely, if we have an existential hypothesis in the
context, we can eliminate it with inversion. Note the use
of the as... pattern to name the variable that Coq
introduces to name the witness value and get evidence that
the hypothesis holds for the witness. (If we don't
explicitly choose one, Coq will just call it witness, which
makes proofs confusing.)
Theorem exists_example_2 : forall n,
(exists m, n = plus 4 m)
-> (exists o, n = plus 2 o).
Proof.
intros n H.
inversion H as [m Hm].
exists (plus 2 m).
apply Hm. Qed.
Prove that "P holds for all x" and "there is no x for
which P does not hold" are equivalent assertions.
Theorem dist_not_exists : forall (X:Type) (P : X -> Prop),
(forall x, P x) -> ~ (exists x, ~ P x).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Prove that existential quantification distributes over
disjunction.
Theorem dist_exists_or : forall (X:Type) (P Q : X -> Prop),
(exists x, P x \/ Q x) <-> (exists x, P x) \/ (exists x, Q x).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Even Coq's equality relation is not actually built in.
It has the following inductive definition.
(We enclose this definition in a module to avoid confusion with the standard library equality (which we have used extensively already).
(We enclose this definition in a module to avoid confusion with the standard library equality (which we have used extensively already).
Module MyEquality.
Inductive eq (A:Type) : A -> A -> Prop :=
refl_equal : forall x, eq A x x.
Notation "x = y" := (eq _ x y) (at level 70, no associativity) : type_scope.
This definition is a bit subtle. The way to think
about it is that, given a set A, it defines a family of
propositions "x is equal to y," indexed by pairs of
values (x and y) from A. There is just one way of
constructing evidence for members of this family: by applying
the constructor refl_equal to two identical arguments.
Here is an alternate definition, from the Coq standard library.
Inductive eq' (A:Type) (x:A) : A -> Prop :=
refl_equal' : eq' A x x.
Notation "x =' y" := (eq' _ x y) (at level 70, no associativity) : type_scope.
Verify that the two definitions of equality are equivalent.
Theorem two_defs_of_eq_coincide : forall (A:Type) x y,
eq A x y <-> eq' A x y.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
The advantage of the second definition is that the
induction principle that Coq derives for it is precisely the
familiar principle of Leibniz equality: what we mean when
we say "x and y are equal" is that every property on A
that is true of x is also true of y.
We've seen inversion used with both equality hypotheses and
hypotheses asserting inductively defined propositions. Now
that we've seen that these are actually the same thing, let's
take a closer look at how inversion behaves...
In general, the inversion tactic
EXAMPLE: If we invert a hypothesis built with and, there is only one constructor, so only one subgoal gets generated. Again, the conclusion (result type) of the constructor -- A /\ B -- doesn't place any restrictions on the form of A or B, so we don't get any extra equalities in the context of the subgoal. The constructor does have two arguments, though, and these can be seen in the context in the subgoal.
EXAMPLE: If we invert a hypothesis built with eq, there is again only one constructor, so only one subgoal gets generated. Now, though, the form of the refl_equal constructor does give us some extra information: it tells us that the two arguments to eq must be equal! The inversion tactic adds this to the context.
In general, the inversion tactic
- takes a hypothesis H whose type is some inductively
defined proposition P
- for each constructor C in P's definition
- generates a new subgoal in which we assume H was
built with C
- adds the arguments (premises) of C to the context of
the subgoal as extra hypotheses
- matches the conclusion (result type) of C against the
current goal and calculates a set of equalities that must
hold in order for C to be applicable
- adds these equalities to the context of the subgoal
- if the equalities are not satisfiable (e.g., they involve things like S n = O, immediately solves the subgoal.
- generates a new subgoal in which we assume H was
built with C
EXAMPLE: If we invert a hypothesis built with and, there is only one constructor, so only one subgoal gets generated. Again, the conclusion (result type) of the constructor -- A /\ B -- doesn't place any restrictions on the form of A or B, so we don't get any extra equalities in the context of the subgoal. The constructor does have two arguments, though, and these can be seen in the context in the subgoal.
EXAMPLE: If we invert a hypothesis built with eq, there is again only one constructor, so only one subgoal gets generated. Now, though, the form of the refl_equal constructor does give us some extra information: it tells us that the two arguments to eq must be equal! The inversion tactic adds this to the context.
A proposition parameterized over a number (like ev)
can be thought of as a predicate -- i.e., it defines a
subset of nat, namely those numbers for which the
proposition is provable. In the same way, a two-argument
proposition can be thought of as a relation -- i.e., it
defines a set of pairs for which the proposition is provable.
In the next few sections, we explore the consequences of this
observation.
We've already seen an inductive definition of one
fundamental relation: equality. Another useful one is the
"less than or equal to" relation on numbers:
This definition should be fairly intuitive. It says
that there are two ways to give evidence that one number is
less than or equal to another: either observe that they are
the same number, or give evidence that the first is less than
or equal to the predecessor of the second.
Inductive le : nat -> nat -> Prop :=
| le_n : forall n, le n n
| le_S : forall n m, (le n m) -> (le n (S m)).
(* Check le_ind. *)
End FirstLe.
This is a fine definition of the <= relation, but we
can streamline it a little by observing that the left-hand
argument n is the same everywhere in the definition, so we
can actually make it a "general parameter" to the whole
definition, rather than an argument to each constructor.
Inductive le (n:nat) : nat -> Prop :=
| le_n : le n n
| le_S : forall m, (le n m) -> (le n (S m)).
Notation "m <= n" := (le m n).
Why is the second one better (even though it looks less
symmetric)? Because it gives us a simpler induction
principle.
(* Check le_ind. *)
By contrast, the induction principle that Coq calculates for
the first definition has a lot of extra quantifiers, which
makes it messier to work with when proving things by
induction. Here is the induction principle for the first
le:
(* Check le_ind. (the first one above) *)
(* ===> le_ind
: forall P : nat -> nat -> Prop,
(forall n : nat, P n n) ->
(forall n m : nat, FirstLe.le n m -> P n m -> P n (S m)) ->
forall n n0 : nat, FirstLe.le n n0 -> P n n0 *)
(* ===> le_ind
: forall P : nat -> nat -> Prop,
(forall n : nat, P n n) ->
(forall n m : nat, FirstLe.le n m -> P n m -> P n (S m)) ->
forall n n0 : nat, FirstLe.le n n0 -> P n n0 *)
Proofs of facts about <= using the constructors
le_n and le_S follow the same patterns as proofs about
predicates, like ev in the previous chapter. We can
apply the constructors to prove <= goals (e.g., to show
that 3<=3 or 3<=6), and we can use tactics like
inversion to extract information from <= hypotheses in
the context (e.g., to prove that ~(2 <= 1).)
Here are some sanity checks on the definition. (Notice that,
although these are the same kind of simple "unit tests" as we
gave for the testing functions we wrote in the first few
lectures, we must construct their proofs explicitly --
simpl and reflexivity don't do the job, because the
proofs aren't just a matter of simplifying computations.
Theorem test_le1 :
3 <= 3.
Proof.
(* WORK IN CLASS *) Admitted.
Theorem test_le2 :
3 <= 6.
Proof.
(* WORK IN CLASS *) Admitted.
Theorem test_le3 :
~ (2 <= 1).
Proof.
(* WORK IN CLASS *) Admitted.
The "strictly less than" relation n < m can now be defined
in terms of le.
A few more simple relations on numbers
Inductive square_of : nat -> nat -> Prop :=
sq : forall n:nat, square_of n (mult n n).
Inductive next_nat (n:nat) : nat -> Prop :=
| nn : next_nat n (S n).
Inductive next_even (n:nat) : nat -> Prop :=
| ne_1 : ev (S n) -> next_even n (S n)
| ne_2 : ev (S (S n)) -> next_even n (S (S n)).
Define an inductive relation total_relation that holds
betfween every pair of natural numbers.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Define an inductive relation empty_relation (on numbers)
that never holds.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
We can define three-place relations, four-place relations,
etc., in just the same way as binary relations. For example,
consider the following three-place relation on numbers:
Inductive R : nat -> nat -> nat -> Prop :=
| c1 : R 0 0 0
| c2 : forall m n o, R m n o -> R (S m) n (S o)
| c3 : forall m n o, R m n o -> R m (S n) (S o)
| c4 : forall m n o, R (S m) (S n) (S (S o)) -> R m n o
| c5 : forall m n o, R m n o -> R n m o.
- Which of the following propositions are provable?
- R 1 1 2
- R 2 2 6
- If we dropped constructor c5 from the definition of R,
would the set of provable propositions change? Briefly (1
sentence) explain your answer.
- If we dropped constructor c4 from the definition of R, would the set of provable propositions change? Briefly (1 sentence) explain your answer.
☐
One of the main purposes of Coq is to prove that programs
match their specifications. To this end, let's prove that
our definition of filter matches a specification. Here is
the specification, written out informally in English.
Suppose we have a set X, a function test: X->bool, and a list l of type list X. Suppose further that l is an in-order merge of two lists, l1 and l2, such that every item in l1 satisfies test and no item in l2 satisfies test. Then filter test l = l1.
Your job is to translate this specification into a Coq theorem and prove it. (Hint: You'll need to begin by defining what it means for one list to be a merge of two others. Do this with an inductive relation, not a Fixpoint.)
Suppose we have a set X, a function test: X->bool, and a list l of type list X. Suppose further that l is an in-order merge of two lists, l1 and l2, such that every item in l1 satisfies test and no item in l2 satisfies test. Then filter test l = l1.
Your job is to translate this specification into a Coq theorem and prove it. (Hint: You'll need to begin by defining what it means for one list to be a merge of two others. Do this with an inductive relation, not a Fixpoint.)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
We've now defined a few particular relations. As you
probably remember from your undergraduate discrete math
course, there are a lot of ways of discussing and describing
relations in general -- ways of classifying relations (are
they reflexive, transitive, etc.), theorems that can be
proved generically about classes of relations, constructions
that build one relation from another, etc. Let us pause here
to review a few of these that will be useful in what
follows.
A relation on a set X is a proposition parameterized by
two Xs -- i.e., it is a logical assertion involving two
values from the set X. (This definition is just giving a
name to the idea that we've been using for the past few
minutes.)
A relation R on a set X is a partial function if, for
every x, there is at most one y such that R x y -- or,
to put it differently, if R x y1 and R x y2 together
imply y1 = y2.
Definition partial_function (X: Type) (R: relation X) :=
forall x y1 y2 : X, R x y1 -> R x y2 -> y1 = y2.
Implicit Arguments partial_function [X].
(* Check partial_function. *)
Now, we can prove that the next_nat relation is a partial
function...
Theorem next_nat_partial_function :
partial_function next_nat.
Proof.
unfold partial_function.
intros x y1 y2 P Q.
inversion P. inversion Q.
reflexivity. Qed.
...but <= is not a partial function.
Show that the total_relation you defined above is not a
partial function.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Show that the empty_relation you defined above is a partial
function.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Definition reflexive (X: Type) (R: relation X) :=
forall a : X, R a a.
Implicit Arguments reflexive [X].
Theorem le_reflexive :
reflexive le.
Proof.
unfold reflexive. intros n. apply le_n. Qed.
Definition transitive (X: Type) (R: relation X) :=
forall a b c : X, (R a b) -> (R b c) -> (R a c).
Implicit Arguments transitive [X].
Theorem le_trans :
transitive le.
Proof.
intros n m o Hnm Hmo.
induction Hmo.
Case "le_n". apply Hnm.
Case "le_S". apply le_S. apply IHHmo. Qed.
Theorem lt_trans:
transitive lt.
Proof.
unfold lt. unfold transitive.
intros n m o Hnm Hmo.
apply le_S in Hnm.
apply le_trans with (a := (S n)) (b := (S m)) (c := o).
apply Hnm.
apply Hmo. Qed.
We can also prove lt_trans more laboriously by induction,
without using le_trans. Do this.
Theorem lt_trans' :
transitive lt.
Proof.
(* Prove this by induction on evidence that m is lesfs than
o *)
unfold lt. unfold transitive.
intros n m o Hnm Hmo.
induction Hmo as [| m' Hm'o].
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Prove the same thing again by induction on o
Theorem lt_trans'' :
transitive lt.
Proof.
unfold lt. unfold transitive.
intros n m o Hnm Hmo.
induction o as [| o'].
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
The transitivity of le, in turn, can be used to prove some
facts that will be useful later (e.g., for the proof of
antisymmetry in the next section)...
Theorem le_Sn_le : forall n m, S n <= m -> n <= m.
Proof.
intros n m H. apply le_trans with (S n).
apply le_S. apply le_n.
apply H. Qed.
☐
Provide an informal proof of the following theorem:
Theorem: For every n, ~(S n <= n)
A formal proof of this is an optional exercise below, but try the informal proof without doing the formal proof first
Proof: (* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Theorem: For every n, ~(S n <= n)
A formal proof of this is an optional exercise below, but try the informal proof without doing the formal proof first
Proof: (* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
☐
Definition symmetric (X: Type) (R: relation X) :=
forall a b : X, (R a b) -> (R b a).
Implicit Arguments symmetric [X].
☐
Definition antisymmetric (X: Type) (R: relation X) :=
forall a b : X, (R a b) -> (R b a) -> a = b.
Implicit Arguments antisymmetric [X].
☐
Definition equivalence (X:Type) (R: relation X) :=
(reflexive R) /\ (symmetric R) /\ (transitive R).
Implicit Arguments equivalence [X].
A relation is called a "partial order" when it's reflexive, antisymmetric, and transitive.
In the Coq standard library it's just "order" for short.
Definition order (X:Type) (R: relation X) :=
(reflexive R) /\ (antisymmetric R) /\ (transitive R).
Implicit Arguments order [X].
(reflexive R) /\ (antisymmetric R) /\ (transitive R).
Implicit Arguments order [X].
A preorder is almost like a partial order, but doesn't have to be antisymmetric.
Definition preorder (X:Type) (R: relation X) :=
(reflexive R) /\ (transitive R).
Implicit Arguments preorder [X].
Theorem le_order :
order le.
Proof.
unfold order. split.
Case "refl". apply le_reflexive.
split.
Case "antisym". apply le_antisymmetric.
Case "transitive.". apply le_trans. Qed.
(reflexive R) /\ (transitive R).
Implicit Arguments preorder [X].
Theorem le_order :
order le.
Proof.
unfold order. split.
Case "refl". apply le_reflexive.
split.
Case "antisym". apply le_antisymmetric.
Case "transitive.". apply le_trans. Qed.
Let's pause briefly to record several facts about the <=
and < relations that we are going to need later in the
course. The proofs make good practice exercises.
Theorem O_le_n : forall n,
0 <= n.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem n_le_m__Sn_le_Sm : forall n m,
n <= m -> S n <= S m.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem le_plus_l : forall a b,
a <= a + b.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem plus_lt : forall n1 n2 m,
plus n1 n2 < m ->
n1 < m /\ n2 < m.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem lt_S : forall n m,
n < m ->
n < S m.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem le_step : forall n m p,
n < m ->
m <= S p ->
n <= p.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem ble_nat_true : forall n m,
ble_nat n m = true -> n <= m.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem ble_nat_n_Sn_false : forall n m,
ble_nat n (S m) = false ->
ble_nat n m = false.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Hint: Do the right induction!
Theorem ble_nat_false : forall n m,
ble_nat n m = false -> ~(n <= m).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
ble_nat n m = false -> ~(n <= m).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐